Sunday, January 4, 2015

National Security Advocacy as a “Moral Judgment”?


            Arnold Wolfers argues that policymakers who “advocate a policy devoted to national security are not always aware of the fact – if they do not explicitly deny it – that they are passing moral judgment when they advise a nation to pursue the goal of national security” because they “[imply], knowingly or not, that more security is sufficiently desirable to warrant such evils as the cut in much-needed social welfare benefits or as the extension of the period of military service” (499). This claim, however, rests on the assumption of a utilitarian moral framework. Alternative construals of morality might cause us to question whether or not policymakers do in fact pass “moral judgment” when they devote money to the national security apparatus at the expense of social welfare programs. If an action is moral or immoral does not necessarily depend on how well it maximizes the sum of people’s happiness, but may instead be concerned with constraints on permitted actions.
            First, it should be demonstrated that Wolfers does indeed approach the subject of moral judgment from a utilitarian perspective. He writes the following: “If someone insists that his country should do more to build up its strength, he is…comparing and weighing values in order to decide which of them are deemed sufficiently good to justify the evil of sacrificing others” (499). Morality becomes an issue once the normative signifier should is used, and the discussion here seems to concern utilitarianism prima facie – i.e., the idea that one ought to maximize benefits for society while minimizing harms. “Compare” and “weigh” are the two key words here because under utilitarianism, actions which seem morally questionable can be justified by virtue of the gains realized by society as a whole.
Whenever people discuss the morality of actions in the context of achieving certain goals, it is a clear sign of utilitarianism at work. After public opinion polls have been collected, different options considered, and computer simulations run, lawmakers can gain a lot of insight regarding policies needed in order to elicit a particular outcome – political, economic, or otherwise. Of course, many of these policies might seem distasteful or even downright immoral. In these situations, the natural response is oftentimes to alter expectations about what kind of goals are achievable. If a nation wants complete security, Wolfers argues it will need to take over the entire world to eliminate external threats, in all likelihood constituting an extreme moral violation. Most nations clearly do not attempt to eliminate so thoroughly all threats to their well-being, and Wolfers states that a policymaker’s “most difficult moral task” is his decision regarding “which level of security to make his target” (500).
            An emphasis on outcomes is not the only lens through which the nature of morality can be viewed, however. In Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Robert Nozick observes that morality can be analyzed in terms of “side constraints upon the actions to be done: don’t violate constraints C…[Actors] may place the nonviolation of rights as a constraint upon action, rather than…building it into the end state to be realized” (30). Given this, Wolfers’ use of the term “moral judgment” seems a bit strong. To use this phrase implies the condemnation of a particular act because it is immoral. Even if some people believe that welfare spending must be cut to reach a level of security deemed optimal for society, they might not believe these reductions take on a decidedly moral quality as long as no side constraints are violated. Certain actions are undoubtedly worthy of our express moral censure. But while making a fiscal sacrifice might be stingy, painful, or otherwise unfortunate, it does not always take on a dimension that can be judged in this way.  
            To phrase things differently, Wolfers talks about morality in terms of the positive actions that policymakers should make, subject to a complicated weighing of potential outcomes. On the other hand, a side constraint view frames the question in terms of what policymakers shouldn’t do, regardless of the consequences. The side constraint view might admittedly break down in extreme cases, and Nozick himself punts the issue: “The question of whether these side constraints are absolute or whether they may be violated in order to avoid catastrophic moral horror…is one I hope largely to avoid” (30).
Discussing the relative merits of the utilitarian versus the side constraint view is far outside the scope of this brief essay. Nonetheless, there is a clear precedent within political theory for thinking about morality differently than Wolfers does, and one can see the potential implications for policymakers. Instead of weighing the costs and benefits of particular “evil” actions, they might ask whether or not said actions may be carried out at all. This question should be considered by those concerned with the ethical implications of new legislation.  

6 comments:

  1. Two ideas from Wolfers’ piece that stood out to me were the idea that total security can never be achieved by a nation and the application of the law of diminishing returns to national security. The idea of not being able to achieve total security seems obvious when laid out by Wolfers but I believe that it is expected by a large segment of the American public. Politicians of either side of the spectrum reinforce this either acting of their own belief in total security or by exploiting a situation for political gain. The idea that total security is impossible is especially evident today with the war on terror where terrorism is waged largely by non state actors and attacks carried out by small cells or “lone wolfs”. After any attack there are always questions of “How could this happen?” or a search for which politician, agency, or branch of government is to blame for letting the attack happen. As Wolfer states, the only way to achieve total security is for a nation to take over the entire world and the U.S. is not capable of taking over the entire world and monitoring all its population for potential threats. Or the costs of raising and supporting an internal police force to monitor and protect against attacks would be too expensive and come at too high a cost to other functions of the state. There have been plenty of intelligence failures but the state cannot remove pressure cookers (Boston bombings), fertilizer (Oklahoma City bombing), or knives (Lee Rigby murder) from the market.
    The law of diminishing returns applied to national security is another concept that seems obvious but not understood by politicians and the general public. How much safer will an additional TSA agent or F-35 make the nation? And would that money be better spent on public health or welfare initiatives? In the wake of threats and attacks the answer always seems to increased defense measures whether it be more troops, better equipment, or law enforcement personnel but it may be the case that the nation hit a point of diminishing returns a long time ago. Policy makers may believe this but push for increased defense measures to avoid confronting this reality or explaining it to the public.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. This comment has been removed by the author.

      Delete
    2. Discussions on diminishing marginal returns play an interesting role in the discussion of utilitarianism, I think. However, some scholars actually argue that certain goods are not, in fact, subject to these diminishing returns. If you're interested in reading such a piece, you can look this paper: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2381290?seq=5#page_scan_tab_contents. Admittedly it's a bit off topic from what we're talking about here, but still interesting.

      In a certain sense, it seems odd to talk about the diminishing marginal returns of security because the notion of security can be construed, unlike the amount of money or other goods that you have, as a dichotomy. That is, you are either secure or insecure. Granted, this construal is limited and it makes more sense to think about security on a sliding scale of sorts, but you still are "completely secure" or "completely insecure" at either end of this scale. No upper bound exists on the amount of money that you can have.

      Another important distinction should also be made. It's not that we VALUE the additional security we gain on the upper end of the sliding scale of security to a lesser degree, it's just that these additional gains in security will cost too much. This seems pretty intuitive if we think about risk in percentage terms. Complete or absolute security is 100% security, and complete lack of security is 0% security.

      Say for example we are 99% secure, that is, we are 99% certain our values will not be attacked. The additional 1% of security might cost us untold billions of dollars to achieve, violate our rights, etc. It's not like we're indifferent to that extra 1% of security, though. One would think that it if obtaining this 1% cost us 1/99th of what the first 99% cost, then we would go for it.

      Delete
    3. Also note that even the cost of taking over the entire world is not enough to guarantee 100% security, as the dominant power then has to face internal threats.

      Delete
  2. Nathan,

    This is very interesting. I do wonder how your critique makes the decision an amoral one. You seem to be arguing that it is not IMMORAL to choose security over social welfare programs but that does not make the decision to value security more than social welfare (or any other good) one that is not imbued with morality. It is still a moral decision. You are just arguing that choosing national security is not immoral.

    ReplyDelete
  3. I do see what you're saying here. Maybe this example will make the point in a different way:

    You are a head of a household who needs to purchase a vehicle to drive your family to and from a particular location. There are two cars you can buy -- a small compact car or a large SUV. You can only afford one or the other. The compact car can give your family pride for making the "green" choice, but the SUV will protect your family more from the external threats faced on the dangerous roads. Certainly there is a vehicle choice that might be better for your family based on a number of different factors, but it seems a bit odd to say that you would pass "moral judgment" on someone who picks the SUV if you think the compact car is better. Some people do not consider end results important when deciding the morality of an action. A choice between national security and social welfare seems like it could take on a similar quality as the compact/SUV choice.

    Granted, you probably aren't really convinced by this, so consider another situation. What if a country is indifferent between (X - Y) dollars worth of social welfare and (X + Y) dollars worth of national security? In this case, it certainly seems odd to say that increasing the national security budget by Y dollars constitutes a moral judgment. There are all sorts of political reasons people might want to shift budgets around, regardless of what the money is actually spent on.

    ReplyDelete